under the patronage of St Joseph and St Dominic By the rivers of Babylon there we sat and wept, remembering Zion; |
|
CHRISTOPHER PEARSON’S MORAL THEOLOGYDownload this document as a PDF There is clearly a defect in the formation of the convert Australian Catholic journalist, Christopher Pearson. In his Op Ed piece for The Australian, 20-21 June 2009, Conservative’s hero a hard man to read, he writes—
The constant teaching of the Catholic Church over 2,000 years contradicts the existence of this alleged right. Thus, in December 1930, Pius XI—
It is precisely because judges have failed to uphold the moral principle at the heart of the matter—the sanctity of human life, of all human life—that western countries like Australia find themselves in their present appalling moral state. The only thing ‘classical’ about the view Pearson defends is the case it embraces, a type used all too frequently by those content to ignore principle for the sake of expediency. Hard cases, as any lawyer will tell him, make bad law. Hard cases provide no excuse for the denial of principle.
Michael Baker ADDENDUMIt has been suggested that Christopher Pearson was referring to the exceptional case covered by the Principle of the Double Effect such as arises, for example, with an ectopic pregnancy. The Principle of the Double Effect provides that it is not licit to perform an act wherefrom flow two effects, the one good, the other evil, unless four conditions are fulfilled:
Now Pearson grounds his opinion on this premise—
That this falls outside the principle can be shown from an analysis of its application. If an ectopic pregnancy was allowed to proceed, there is no ‘either/or’ about the issue. Its continuance would kill BOTH mother and child because the child is developing in an organ other than the womb. The principle allows the removal of the fallopian tube to save the life of the mother: the death of the child, though it is an inevitable consequence, is not intended: nor can any guilt attach when the operation is performed. Similarly, there is no 'either/or' about the issue confronting the fighter pilot who shoots down an airliner commandeered by Muslim extremists before it collides with a skyscraper. If the pilot does not act, BOTH passengers and the occupants of the building will be killed. If he does act the lives of those in the building will be saved. Pearson’s remarks can only be taken to refer to the situation of the difficult childbirth where the life of the mother is threatened.[2] It is not licit, in such a case, to prefer the life of either, as Pius XI makes clear. Pearson is wrong again in the assertion contained in his next sentence—
The evidence is overwhelmingly against him. It is not a matter of “moral theology” building on this extreme case, but the public perception (manifested in the country's laws) building on it. Because of the influence of Protestantism rather than Catholicism on the thinking of English legislators, statute law in England in the early 20th century was modified to protect a surgeon who intervened to kill an unborn child whose birth threatened the life of the mother. The betrayal of moral principle entailed here was incorporated into legislation in Australia shortly afterwards. With this permission, it became licit to kill in some circumstances. Thenceforth the rule of morals was no longer absolute. Once you admit a principle, the consequences flow. The law having admitted the principle that evil may be done that good may come of it, the foundation was laid for the granting of greater, and greater, concessions. The judges of England and Australia extended them after Dr Aleck Bourne, an English gynaecologist, decided to test the law by aborting a young girl raped by four guardmen in 1938. He was acquitted in a celebrated trial (Rex v Bourne). Now, in the early 21st century, we have reached the point where any alleged threat to the mother's wellbeing will suffice to permit her to kill her unborn child. It is impossible to police these claims and the inevitable consequence is with us: abortion on demand. It is little consolation to the world that Dr Bourne later repented of the action he had taken. But the harm was done not by him, but by the influence of Protestantism on English and Australian legislative thinking. However, let us concede the point that Mr Pearson may have intended to refer only to cases covered by the Principle of the Double Effect, and that he has expressed himself badly. Who among his readers, the vast majority of them secular and atheistic, would know that he was referring to a principle whose application is so carefully surrounded with conditions? And why did he not make it clear, if this is what he was referring to? At the very least his remarks are misleading. At worst, they are a scandal. MJB |